Homogeneous Beliefs and Speculation
in Asset Pricing Paradigms



© Copyright 2007 by Michael A. S. Guth. All Rights Reserved. No portion of this site, including the contents of this web page may be copied, retransmitted, reposted, or duplicated in significant portion without the express written permission of Dr. Michael Guth. Users are always welcome to establish links to this web page or to quote from it freely.

MICHAEL A. S. GUTH, Ph.D., J.D.
Professor of Financial Economics and Law
send e-mail
(E-mail is quickest method of contact).
  116 Oklahoma Ave.
  Oak Ridge, TN
  37830-8604
  Phone: (865) 483-8309


Financial Economics Homepage      ||       Attorney at Law Homepage

 

cite as Michael A. S. Guth, "Homogeneous Beliefs and Speculation in Asset Pricing Paradigms," Chapter 5 in Michael A. S. Guth, SPECULATIVE BEHAVIOR AND THE OPERATION OF COMPETITIVE MARKETS UNDER UNCERTAINTY, Avebury Ashgate Publishing, Aldorshot, England (1994), ISBN 1856289850.

Permission of Avebury Ashgate Publishing to post this chapter on the michaelguth.com website is gratefully acknowledged. Unfortunately, the figures contained in the book would not display properly on this web page. However, the book can be purchased from Amazon or from this site

 

 

Homogeneous Beliefs and Speculation
in Asset Pricing Paradigms

 

 

        [A] major problem of finance theory is an overreliance on the assump­tion of common beliefs.  I have a suspicion, (and it is only a suspi­cion), that this assumption is behind the failure of theory to explain much of the observed empirical behavior in markets.  It is difficult, however, to figure out how to proceed in relaxing this assumption.

                                      Richard Roll, 1988

 

5.1.  Introduction[1]

 

Most asset pricing theories assume investors hold common or homoge­neous beliefs.  These assumptions permit theorists to aggregate individual valuation formulas into a market-level expression.  Recently, common knowledge belief assumptions have begun replacing the older homogeneous beliefs assumptions.  If beliefs are common knowledge, then everyone knows everyone knows .... everyone's beliefs.  Without common knowledge assump­tions, investors in these models face intrinsic uncertainty over which firms the rest of the market regarded as undervalued or overvalued.  Investors might also face uncertainty over how the market's beliefs will change with the arrival of new information.  This uncertainty can affect future prices; consequently, it figures in any capital gains (loss) estimate.

    Stock prices largely reflect real earnings for the past year coupled with expected earnings for the out year or two.  Investor beliefs partially determine forecasts for future earnings and play an even larger role in the equilibrium price-to-earnings ratio for each firm's stock.  This chapter examines whether Modigliani-Miller (MM) arbitrage, the Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM), and Ross's Arbitrage Pricing Theory (APT) need to employ common knowledge investor belief assumptions.

    Although we could apply these concepts to any asset valuation theory, this chapter emphasizes the celebrated Modigliani-Miller (1958) paradigm.  The MM arbitrage strategy has a common thread to most of the other asset pricing theories.  The paradigm's thirty year anniversary in 1988 spawned several MM theory retrospectives, which surprisingly omitted any discussion of embedded common knowledge assumptions in the model.

    Concerning the informational structure of the paradigm, Miller (1988) writes `one of the key assumptions of both the leverage and dividend models (was) that all capital market participants, inside managers and outside investors alike, have the same information about the firm's cash flows.'  Once this assumption is relaxed, it is well known that the MM results do not hold under asymmetric information.  An extensive literature deals with this issue dating back to Ross (1977a) and Leland and Pyle (1977),[2]  who showed how managers with inside information might have incentives to `signal' the market about the firm's future earnings through either the firm's debt-equity ratio or dividend policy.  In general, this literature focuses on the related topic of managerial incentives but does not explore the theoretical underpinnings of the MM propositions.

    Recent developments on common knowledge raise questions about the robustness of the MM results as the model is currently formu­lated.  How are the MM results affected if investors agree (on the cash flows of a firm) without knowing they agree?[3]  Would some investors want to speculate that the market diverges from their own beliefs?  Stiglitz (1969, 1974) has argued that the MM paradigm remains valid even if heteroge­neous beliefs are admitted into the model.  However, his two-period (1969) model was inadequate to consider the problems posed by speculation, where traders plan to buy and resell knowing information will arrive before the state of the world is revealed.  His multiperiod (1974) model conveniently assumes that all the well-known aggregation  problems with diverse individual beliefs have somehow sorted themselves out, and the economy starts in a market-clearing equilibrium.

    Our analysis can be distinguished from the older, pre-common knowledge era literature on asymmetric information.  The older literature examined the impact of heterogeneous beliefs based on insider information, with managers or existing shareholders better informed than the rest of the market.  This chapter focuses on an MM world in which everyone is equally well informed.  Investors in our formulation will not know if their beliefs are homogeneous or heterogeneous.

    In studying the role of common knowledge in the MM paradigm, one finds a gap even in modern restatements of debt-equity irrelevancy.  Modern restatements are based on income ar­bitrage:  people switching from one asset to another to achieve a greater cash flow from earnings. In fact, they can also receive cash flows from capital gains.  For example, speculation and capital gains considerations do not enter into the following analysis.

 

        The values of debt and equity, in turn, are based on the cash flows that are expected to go to each.  Since the cash flow of the firm must go either to debt or to equity and since linearity assures us that the sum of their values is the value of the sum of their cash flows, it follows that the total value of the firm depends simply on the total cash flow to the firm, regardless of the debt-equity mix chosen by that firm.  Ross (1988), p.128.

 

Intelligent investors know the market values of firms depend on more than just accounting identities; market values depend on (changing) beliefs about the future.  We will assess the impact these speculative considerations have on MM-style arbitrage, the CAPM, and the APT.

    The CAPM is an equilibrium model, whereas the MM paradigm and the APT are arbitrage models.[4]  The absence of arbitrage opportunities permits market clearing in the latter two models.  The reader may be surprised to learn that we find the MM paradigm does not require investor beliefs to be common knowledge.  The CAPM implicitly makes beliefs common knowledge by endowing investors with perfect foresight about asset returns.  The APT needs common knowledge belief assumptions for its validity.  Thus the need for common knowledge belief assumptions depends on features of individual models, not on the equilibrium solution concept.

    Section 5.2 discusses MM's attempts to deal with intrinsic uncertainty and explains how it might lead to speculative invest­ments in the opposite direction of income arbitrage.  Section 5.3 illustrates the logical intuition in the original MM framework.  Section 5.4 presents a numerical example again based on the MM paradigm.  The necessity for common knowledge belief assumptions is examined for the Capital Asset Pricing Model in Section 5.5 and for Ross's Arbitrage Pricing Theory in Section 5.6.  Section 5.5 derives the CAPM from basic constructs; most finance textbooks merely state the CAPM without deriving it.  Section 5.7 examines whether the MM and APT pardigms can incorporate heterogeneous beliefs, as some have suggested, and remain valid.  Section 5.8 presents our conclusions and some observations about real world arbitrage.


5.2.  MM's Missing Assumption and Speculative Investment

 

MM-style arbitrage opportunities imply that when securities are either undervalued or overvalued, an investor should be able to buy and sell stocks and bonds in such a way that he increases the income he would have received from his original portfolio position.  In focusing on income, MM neglected the capital gains motive. 

    MM sensed their original proof of the debt-equity propositions left open the possibility for price speculation.  Although some investor personally regards a firm as overvalued, he may fear the rest of the market views that same firm as fair valued or even undervalued.  That concern led MM to include a missing `imputed rationality' assumption in their subsequent (1961) dividend paper:

 

        [W]e shall say that an individual trader `imputes rationality' to the market or satisfies the postulate of `imputed rationality' if, in forming expectations, he assumes that every other trader in the market is (a) rational in the previous sense of preferring more wealth to less regardless of the form an increment in wealth may take, and (b) imputes rationality to all other traders... Our postulate thus rules out, among other things, the possibility of speculative `bubbles'...  MM (1961).

 

    By imputed rationality, MM sought to eliminate self-fulfilling equilibria, in which investors take dividends into account simply because they believe others will do so.  MM obviously intended that subse­quent formulations of the capital structure paradigm assume imputed rationality as well.  Since prices are determined endogenously in capital markets, the beliefs of market participants will materially affect each person's own opportunity set, whether these beliefs hold that debt-equity ratios, dividends, or sunspots are relevant to firm valuations.   

    This missing assumption appears to have been noted by only one previous paper in the vast MM literature:

 

        MM clearly read much more into this assumption than a statement of the assumption seems to warrant....Thus by `rationality' MM apparently mean than an individual ignores capital gains aspects of security purchases - but this is never stated explicitly....And what this amounts to is an assump­tion that individuals behave in the market on the basis of earnings expectations (income prospects) and not on the basis of wealth considerations based on prospective future values of shares or bonds....[W]hen an obviously important (and perhaps dominant) feature or aspect of behavior is assumed away, or must be assumed away, to prove a proposition, there is a presumption of problems for the proposition itself.  We might also note that MM agree their use of the term `rational' to refer to behavior based solely on the earnings prospects is much more debatable than, say, the use of the term `rational' to refer to consistent behavior by consumers in (economic theory).  Burness, Cummin­gs, and Quirk (1980), pp.40-42.

 

    Stiglitz (1974) previously spoke about problems with self-fulfilling equilibria when he concluded `if individuals believe that financial policy affects firm valuation, then it will.'  Without using the term `common knowledge,' Stiglitz nevertheless implied that a common knowledge beliefs assumption was required to prevent `expectations of real returns dependent on firm financial policy.'  An interested reader would be left confused as to whether Stiglitz was assuming the very object of his proof:  debt-equity ratios are irrelevant.

    But in the final analysis, after more than two dozen separate proofs in alternative variants of the original MM model, the MM literature concluded that investor beliefs must be homogeneous (as to firm earnings and therefore risk classes) and common knowledge.  Otherwise, the MM propositions were susceptible to disproofs of the kind outlined below:

 

        Stiglitz (1974) seems to argue that only if investors think that financial policy will affect the `real' returns -- presumably earnings and/or dividends of a firm -- will this be a factor in determining market value.  But of course all that is required for financial policy to affect market value is the belief on the part of any investors that other investors value firms in part on the basis of the debt-equity ratio of the firm, regardless of whether the financial policy has any effect at all on earnings and/or dividends....Stiglitz is underestimat­ing the importance of the problems posed by speculative consider­ations so far as the MM proposition is concerned.  We are in what might be called an emperor's clothes situation; the MM proposition is correct only so long as all investors believe it is correct, and once any non-infinitesimal group of investors believes it is wrong, it is wrong.  In order to clear the air, and settle the matter once and for all, we would like to announce that we do not believe the MM proposition is correct.  Since we have modest (but non-infini­tesimal) investments in the market, we have now disproved the theorem.  We would be interested in alternative proofs  that bypass


        the problems posed by our approach.  Burness, Cummings, and Quirk (1980), pp. 63-65.

 

     We agree with the reasoning of Burness, Cummings, and Quirk, but not their conclusion.[5]  The above quotation correctly points out that in a multiperiod economy the absence of common knowledge can lead investors to speculate in a manner differing from the arbitrage predicted by the MM literature.[6]  However, even if some non-infini­tes­imal group believes debt-equity ratios matter, the MM strategy continues to lock in a sure-profit, provided the investor can hold his position long enough for earnings to be reported.  This group's actions in no way eliminate the arbitrage opportunities available in the market.  Thus, markets would not clear.  Fluctuations in security prices during the intermediate periods -before earnings are realized - represent an opportunity cost, not a real loss.[7]

 

 

5.3.  Capital Gains in the Original MM Model

 

Ross (1989) describes how more modern developments in arbitrage pricing have improved the original MM formula­tion of their paradigm. However, the original MM formulation is easier to understand than much of the modern theory.[8]  This section the capital gains motive in the original MM framework.  Let Xis denote the earnings of firm i in state of the world s, ei the price of firm i's shares, and Si the total number of shares.  Suppose firm 1 and firm 2 belong to the same risk class:  X1s = c X2s, across every state s.  For simplicity, set the constant c = 1, so that

                                             X1s = X2s / Xs.                                      (5.1)

    Let the first firm be capitalized with only equity so that its market value V1 = E1 = e1 S1, while the second firm has both debt and equity so that its market value V2 = e2 S2 + B2.  Suppose V1 < V2.  MM showed that owners of firm 2 shares could sell off their holdings, purchase shares in firm 1, and achieve higher cash flows for the same dollar investment.

    To see this, let some investor hold α% of firm 2's outstanding stock.  Then the income, Y2s, the investor receives from his firm 2 shares in state of the world s is

                       Y2s = α (X2s - r2 B2)

                           = α (Xs - r2 B2),                                                       (5.2)

where r2 is the market rate of return firm 2 must pay on its bonds.  Suppose the investor sells his shares in firm 2 and borrows α B2 dollars using these combined proceeds to invest in firm 1 shares.  Let β denote the percentage of firm 1 shares he purchases.  Thus

                                   β E1 = α (e2 S2 + B2) = α V2.

The income he receives from holding these shares in firm 1 and paying interest on his borrowed funds, again noting that X1s / Xs, is

                              Y1s    = β Xs - α r2 B2

                                      = (α V2/E1) Xs - α r2 B2

                                      = α [(V2/V1) Xs - r2 B2]                                 (5.3)

    Since V2 > V1 by hypothesis, then from comparing (5.2) and (5.3), Y1s > Y2s for every state of the world s.  Thus all investors find it profit­able, whatever their preferences toward risk, to sell their `overvalued' shares in firm 2 and acquire shares in the `undervalued' firm 1.  So far so good from an income perspective.

    A few comments are in order on the nature of the MM riskless profit.  First, as already mentioned, it assumes the investor will not have to liquidate his holdings before realizing the earnings Xs in some future period s.  Second, equation (5.3) contains the term r2, which implies the `homemade leverage' idea that individuals can borrow at the same rate as firms.  For the arbitrage trading group of a commercial or investment bank, this assump­tion is trivial.  For individual investors in the real world, this assumption generally will not hold.

    But what happens if the investor wants to continue holding the overvalued firm 2 shares, or even buy additional firm 2 shares, because he believes he can realize an intermediate capital gain before the state is revealed in some future period.  Let ET(Vi) denote the individual's conditional expectation for the market value of firm i in period T given the value of Vi in period 1.  If the same investor believes

 

                        α [ET(V2) - V2] - β [ET(V1) - V1] > Y1s - Y2s                (5.4)

 

then he may hold the overvalued shares with the speculative intent of realizing an intermediate capital gain.  This combined treatment of capital gains and wealth apart from income is largely missing in both the MM literature and the arbitrage pricing literature to date.

    A few comments are also necessary about condition (5.4).  The expectation operator in (5.4) would typically be conditioned on the individual's information set.  However, to assure that everyone has access to the same information, we have restricted the information set to the publicly known market values in period 1.  Even with the inequality expressed in (5.4), the fact remains that Y1s > Y2s, and others in the market will want to exploit this arbitrage condition.  Therefore, expression (5.4) suggests why someone may seek intermediate capital gains, but it fails to eliminate the arbitrage opportunities, a condition necessary for market clearing in the MM world.

 

 

5.4.  A Numerical Example

 

This numerical example will first derive conditions under which an investor may want to continue holding `overvalued' shares in a firm.  Second, we will show that under these conditions, an arbitrage opportunity exists - even if the investor still wants to hold the overvalued shares.  Consider two firms, Firm A and Firm B, with identical earnings per share of either 1, 2, 3, 4, or 5 and a sequence of events as follows.  Initially traders have a prior round equilibrium based solely on their prior beliefs for earnings.  Then after markets have cleared, Firm A changes its debt-equity ratio.  The markets reopen and trading resumes.  After markets have again closed, Firm B will announce a change in its debt-equity ratio.  Trading resumes followed by information on the actual earnings of the two firms. 

    Just as in the original MM model, let all market participants have access to the same information and share `homogeneous beliefs' in the form of a common prior over the five possible states for earnings/share.[9]  Define this common prior as Pr(1) = 0.6, Pr(2) = 0.1, Pr(3) = 0.2, Pr(4) = 0, and Pr(5) = 0.1, where Pr(s) denotes the common probability assigned to earnings/share s.

    With the prior belief distribution (.6, .1, .2, 0, .1), the market fundamental[10] of this firm's equity is 6 in period 0.  To simplify the calculations, suppose both firms' shares trade at a price/earnings ratio of 10.  Thus in the prior trading round, both Firm A and B shares clear the market at a price of $19.  Next suppose Firm A changes its debt-equity ratio, and this change is publicly announced (so everyone has access to the same information).  Suppose some non-infinitesimal group decides that debt-equity ratios matter to them, and they are willing to sell Firm A shares now for $17/share.  The rest of the market would willingly purchase from the group at that price, i.e., the group could easily find one or more trading partners.  Therefore, this group may sell their block of shares in Firm A at $17/share.  The price of Firm B shares continues to rest at $19/share.

    For the rest of the market Firm A shares now look undervalued relative to Firm B shares, and the MM arbitrage strategy suggests selling off Firm B shares and borrowing to buy Firm A shares until the two shares are again selling for the same price.  Any price discrepancy between these two firm's share prices is an arbitrage opportunity.  MM define their equilibrium as the absence of arbitrage for any investor.  This arbitrage exists by virtue of the firms having the same earnings across possible states of the world; the lack of common knowledge about investor prior beliefs in no way limits the arbitrage.  Thus, while some block of shares may trade at $17/share, this price cannot remain the market clearing price in this period.  Firm A shares will most likely be bid up again to $19/share.

    If we pursue the numerical example further, we may illuminate some features of condition (5.4).  We see from the prior distribution (.6, .1, .2, 0, .1) that investors assign the most probability to earnings/share equal to 1.  However, suppose some individual believes that other people believe the earnings/share will most likely turn out to be 3.  In that case, both Firm A and Firm B shares will eventually sell for $30/share.  Applying these numbers to condition (5.4), and noting the $2 price discrepancy, would yield

                                       .                               (5.5)

For condition (5.5) to be met,  would have to be much greater than  :  Firm A must have many fewer shares outstanding than Firm B.  Even then the condition does not guarantee any individual will actually speculate on capital gains.  Finally, if both Firms A and B did not trade at $30/share when they both report earnings of $3/share, then they would not belong to the same risk class (assuming c = 1 in equation (5.1)).  Thus another of the MM assumptions would have been violated.

 

 

5.5.  The Capital Asset Pricing Model

 

Like the MM paradigm, common knowledge prior beliefs are not required for the standard formulation of the Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM).  The CAPM, developed by Sharpe (1964), Mossin (1966), Lintner (1969), and others, equates market demand (given expected returns) with the supply of assets to solve for equilibrium prices.  In practice, finance professionals have frequently taken prices in real financial markets as given and then used the  of the CAPM to compute the return expected on individual assets (compared to the overall market's return).

    The empirical assignment of CAPM betas to firms has proven useful for guiding investment choices and evaluating the performance of firms.  In other respects, the CAPM theory had widely disconfirmed implications, e.g., that everyone should hold exactly the same proportionate mix of stocks in the risky portion of his portfolio.  Other implications of the CAPM, such as quadratic utility functions so that individuals are guided soley by the mean and variance of an asset's return or independent and normally distributed asset returns, have also been disproved.

    This section explains why investors in the CAPM paradigm do not face intrinsic uncertainty.  The CAPM assumes investor beliefs are homogeneous but not common knowledge.  Significantly, our finding thus negates the claim that theorists needed or meant to `common knowledge beliefs' for `homogeneous beliefs' all along.

    The `homogeneous beliefs' assumption has crucially simplified mean-variance asset pricing theory and related empirical works.  By homogeneous beliefs financial theorists assume

 

        every investor attaches the same values for the mean  and standard deviation  for the distribution of returns of every security and for the correlations  among the returns.  It follows from this that the opportunity sets of all individuals have the same proportionate shape, differing from one another by only the scale factor of individual endowed capital .  (Hirshleifer (1970), p.289)

 

    Although Sharpe (1964) acknowledged the homogeneous beliefs assumption was `highly restrictive and undoubtedly unrealistic,' he nevertheless defended its use.  `Since these assumptions imply equilibrium conditions which form a major part of classical financial doctrine, it is far from clear that this formulation should be rejected - especially in view of the dearth of alternative models leading to similar results.'  (Sharpe (1964), p.434)

    The two-period CAPM assumes investors know the return on assets, and this return includes both dividends and capital gains potential.  Now purchases and sales of assets by other investors clearly affect everyone's opportunity set.  Therefore, implicitly, investors in the CAPM must know the purchasing behavior of the rest of the market.  Otherwise, they could not calculate with certainty any asset's expected capital gains (losses).  Common knowledge beliefs assumptions would eliminate speculative changes in market prices due to changing beliefs.  The two-period CAPM has substituted perfect knowledge (and indeed common knowledge) about capital gains in place of an agreed common knowledge beliefs assumption over the possible states of the world.  Actually, the two assumptions are logically equivalent.

    The multiperiod CAPM, derived by Merton (1973) and extended by Breeden (1979), assumes price trajectories into the future are known.  It can be shown that intermediate period prices are common knowledge in period 0 only when individuals have agreed common knowledge priors (ACKP) about the state space.  Without ACKP individuals might not reach consensus agreement about what future prices will prevail.  In contrast, the two-period CAPM eliminates intrinsic uncertainty by assuming individuals know the correct capital gains value of assets.

    In his classic beauty contest analogy, Kenyes (1936) reveals why estimates about other investors beliefs are crucial to stock market speculation.  Since stock market investors realize other investors revise their portfolios according to changes or perceived changes in market expectations, investors need to choose stocks which they think average opinion thinks average opinion thinks will perform well.  This thought process is known as `metathinking.'  In general, investors second and third-order beliefs could differ, and consequently one would expect investors to hold differing quantities of a given asset depending on which higher-order beliefs guide their portfolio revision.

    Both the two-period and multiperiod CAPM cleverly avoid financial metathinking behavior by simply assuming investors know the assets' returns with certainty.  Once they know these returns, which may depend on higher-order beliefs or a lack thereof, they have all the information they need to minimize the variance of their portfolios for a given expected return.

    Chapter 4 showed that when investors agree without knowing they agree, intrinsic uncertainty is still present.  If CAPM investors agreed on assets' returns without knowing they agree, one might expect speculative trades to arise in the CAPM as well.  Keynes would argue that stock market investors cannot know assets' returns unless they know the higher-order beliefs of other market traders.  The CAPM simply assumes that do know the returns.  Let us turn now to a derivation of the CAPM and see where investor belief assumptions enter the model.

    The standard CAPM equation derives from the minimization problem,

                                  (5.6)

where  represents the proportion of individual k's portfolio held in asset i;  and  are the returns on assets i and j, respectively, where the return denotes the summed capital gain, dividends, and interest payments divided by the asset's price when the period commenced;   is the Lagrange multiplier associated with individual k's wealth,  is the riskless rate of interest, and  is a constant denoting individual k's expected return on his portfolio.

    The first-order interior condition stated for individual k is

                      .              (5.7)

Let  denote the fraction of total market wealth individual k holds.  Then

                                                                         (5.8)

and

                                                                                    (5.9)

where   denotes asset j's  fraction in  the  total market portfolio, and

  is the market's return on all assets taken together.  Multiplying each term in (5.7) by , summing over k, and substituting (5.8) into the first term after switching the order of summation yields

               23      (5.10)

    Next, we substitute (5.9) into (5.10) and let the variable Z denote .  Then the first-order condition becomes

                                                          (5.11)

Let  and observe that (5.11) is now

                                                              (5.12)

and solving for Z yields

                                                              (5.13)

Again substituting this value of Z into (5.11) yields the familiar CAPM equation:

                                                 (5.14)

                                                                              (5.15)

    This result only requires investors to use, e.g., the same estimate for asset i's return, .  In equilibrium, when all agents revise their portfolios according to their beliefs about the returns, they will have mean-variance efficient holdings.

    The expected value operator in equation (5.6) would likely be conditioned on each individual's information set.  However, since the CAPM assumes investors know the returns, these expected (future) values are known constants, rather than some expected value over a genuine probability distribution.  Again, the CAPM effectively eliminates any source for speculating over the beliefs of others.

 

 

5.6.  Arbitrage Pricing Theory

 

    The Arbitrage Pricing Theory (APT), introduced by Ross (1976) and (1977b), has now received considerable attention as an alternative to the CAPM.  Like the MM model, the APT assumes investors have common prior beliefs.  However, unlike the MM paradigm, the APT actually needs the more restrictive agreed common knowledge priors (ACKP) assumption for its validity.

    The APT in its present form yields nonunique solutions to the market pricing model.  Without common knowledge assumptions, the APT yields individual asset pricing equations that cannot guarantee that the rest of the market uses the same or even similar pricing relationships.

    The logic behind the APT might be expressed as follows.  The returns on a subset of assets in the market are governed by an M-factor model.  Unfortunately, neither the list of factors, nor the specification, nor the subset of assets are ever definitively identified in the APT literature.  This lack of a logical structure has led to numerous empirical problems, but we will focus here on the theoretical model.

    The APT assumes investors have `homogeneous' beliefs about the factor model generating asset returns.  As Roll and Ross (1980) have suggested, `[t]he key point in aggregation is to make strong enough assumptions on the homogeneity of individual anticipations to produce a testable theory.  To do so with the APT we need to assume that individuals agree on both the factor coefficients, , and the expected returns,  '  Ross (1976) at page 356 indicated that the topic of investor belief assumptions is `one of the most difficult and important areas for future research.'  Ross concluded that relaxing the homogeneous expectations assumption would require study of disequilibrium dynamics and movement from ex ante expectations to ex post observations.

    Since its introduction in 1976, the APT has been refined and extended by Huberman (1982), Chamberlain and Rothschild (1983), and Ingersoll (1984), among others.[11]  Subsequently, Dybvig (1983) and Grinblatt and Titman (1983) independently derived upper bounds on the deviations from APT-predicted prices.

    All of these papers begin with the same underlying assumption that asset returns are generated by a factor model.[12]  Consider a market with Z risky assets and a riskless asset with return .  There exists a subset of the assets numbered 1 through T whose returns are governed by the factor model

                                            (5.16)

where  = the return of asset j;  = the information set, upon which the expected value is conditioned;  = sensitivity of asset j's return to movements in factor k;  = mean zero idiosyncratic risk component of the jth asset, j = 1, ..., T.  Assume that the error terms, , are independent of the factors, the returns, and of each other.  Therefore,  = 0 for all .  Further assume that T > M, in order to ensure that the system of equations is determined.

    Our model depicts the standard form of the APT with the addition of the information set .[13]  The theoretical intuition behind the APT is that for some subset of the assets under consideration, the returns will be a linear function of the factors in equation (5.16).  In practice, these factors are `grand aggregates' such as the employment level or the interest rate.  Conversely stated, the APT implies that for a large enough subset of assets, the only possible common determinants of their returns could be the various grand aggregates, although empirical studies reveal little agreement on what these factors should be.

    Each individual formulates his own measure of the market's expected return from assets.  Under the homogeneous beliefs assumption investors in the APT, investors might agree on the returns and the M-factor model without knowing they agree.  The intrinsic uncertainty in the APT can lead investors to question what factors, functional relationship, or information the rest of the market employs in deciding market values for assets.

    An investor in the APT knows what factors and relationships he personally believes will affect asset returns, but he faces risk over the factors and relationships others feel are important.  Consider now the following three factor equations.  All three are possible candidates for the unknown factor model employed by the market, and all three are perfectly consistent with the existing assumptions of the APT.

    First, we have

                                         (5.17)

where the number of factors M-K is less than the M factors in (5.16).  Second,

                                              (5.18)

where  and third

                                             (5.19)

The intrinsic uncertainty present in the original formulation of the APT would not allow any investor to exclude the possibility that other investors in the market employ any or all of these three factor models.

    The first example (5.17) altered the number of factors believed to determine asset returns.  Shanken (1982) has pointed out that financial economists have yet to determine empirically the precise number of factors in the APT.  The statistical data on asset returns often reveal the great majority of variance to be explained by a single factor, and that the other factors though containing significant coefficients nevertheless account for a negligible amount of the variance.[14]  If both the APT and the CAPM explain the variance in asset returns with primarily one factor, then these empirical observations raise questions about the utility of switching from the CAPM to the APT.

        The specification problems encountered in trying to test the APT support the notion that the APT is not common knowledge, even among financial econometricians or arbitrage pricing specialists.  The econometricians may have homogeneous beliefs; they may agree that an M-factor linear model governs asset returns.  Yet uncertainty over what variables and factors the rest of the market might regard as relevant has led each of them to test for the significance of factors presumably not contained in their original M-factor model.  The uncertainty over relevant factors faced by empirical researchers mirrors the uncertainty faced by investors in the APT model even under the homogeneous beliefs assumption.[15]

    The second example (5.18) has replaced the factor coefficients, because although investors may objectively agree on the values of these coefficients, they do not know the values other investors assign to these coefficients.  Again the empirical literature has arrived at no consensus on the factor coefficients.  This lack of empirical agreement might well be explained by theoretical intrinsic uncertainty that investors do not know, and know everyone else knows, what the true coefficients are in the market model.

    Finally, the third factor model (5.19) illustrates this same point for the expected returns.  When  in the third model, an investor believes he is better informed than at least some subset of the market; conversely, if , an investor feels the market has additional information upon which to condition their expectation for the asset's return.

    This section has been based on work published by Guth and Philippatos (1987).  The latter work contains propositions that state (1) the sum of squared deviations from (5.16) is not bounded above as the number of assets increases; (2) the APT has multiple equilibria consistent with the homogeneous beliefs assumption; and (3) that imposing ACKP will yield a unique expression for the APT.

    Finally, we conclude the section by noting that the standard APT return expression is a linear equation, and the APT cannot account for nonlinear relationships through interpreting the factors in the APT as nonlinear functions of real variables.  Without common knowledge assumptions, any individual could personally believe these factors affect returns in a linear form but feel the rest of the market employs a nonlinear relationship.[16]

 

 

5.7.  Heterogeneous Beliefs in the MM and APT Paradigms 

 

Stiglitz (1969, 1974) and Stambaugh (1983) maintained that the MM and APT models, respectively, are valid even if investors have heterogeneous beliefs.  We will consider their arguments sequentially.

    In claiming to have generalized the original MM framework to include heterogeneous beliefs, Stiglitz asserts

 

        No assumption about the source of uncertainty is required.  In particular, the distinction between technological uncertainty and price uncertainty...is of no consequence here. ...The argument of the proof does not require that individuals have the same expectations.  The only agreement in expectations that is required is that the firm will not go bankrupt in any state of nature.  Stiglitz (1974), p.861, 861n.

 

Stiglitz's claim that price uncertainty has no more consequence than technological uncertainty sounds suspicious.  He seems to have overlooked speculative investments based on the unknown beliefs of others.  But Stiglitz (1988) subsequently qualified his own remarks.

 

        It is often the unstated rather than the stated assumptions of a model which are critical, and so it is in the case of the MM theorems.  A critical unstated assumption is that all market participants have full and equal information concerning the returns to the firm.  However, the existence of asymmetric information gives rise to two problems:  current owners may wish to convince potential borrowers that the firm is worth more; and managers can take actions which affect the returns to those who provide capital.  Stiglitz (1988) pp. 123-124.[17]

 

    Given the caveats that investors (1) assign zero probability to any firm going bankrupt and (2) have full and equal information concerning the returns to the firm, we will impose heterogeneous beliefs on Stiglitz's model and see whether the MM irrelevancy theorems still hold.  Table 5.1 defines a subset of the variables used by Stiglitz.


     Table 5.1.  List of Relevant Variables in Stiglitz's (1974) Model

__________________________________________­___________________­

Symbol        Definition

_____________________________________________________________

P j(θ(t))       the probability investor j assigns to state θ(t).        

 

       the profits to firm i at time t in state of the world .      

 

p(t,τ)          the price at time t in state θ(t) of a bond which prom­ises to pay 1 dollar at time τ.

 

Bi(t,τ)         the number of bonds for firm i outstanding at the end of period t with maturity at time τ.

 

B j(t,τ)         the j th individual's ownership of bonds maturing at time τ.

 

Ei(t)             the value of the shares outstanding in the i th firm at the end of period t.

 

αij(t) = Eij(t)/Ei(t), is the fraction of the i th firm held by the j th individual at the end of period t.

__________________________________________________­__________­­

 

 

    Two market clearing conditions characterize an equilibrium.  The first states that ownership of shares in the i th firm equals the value of its equity:

 

                              1                  (5.20)

The second equates demand and supply of bonds at each maturity, :

                                   2                        (5.21)

Note that condition (5.20) is equivalent to

 

    Stiglitz's main theorem then states if (1) no firm goes bankrupt in any state of nature,[18] (2) the economy contains a liquid market for perfectly safe bonds of all maturities, (3) all firms have chosen their financing policy, (4) given a set of feasible consumption paths, every consumer always selects the same consumption path, and (5) the market is in a general equilibrium with all markets clearing; then there exists another general equilibrium in which any firm or group of firms has changed its financial policy, but in which the value of the firms and the price of all bonds of all maturities are unchanged.  Individuals have adjusted their portfolios as follows:

                            3                 (5.22)

i.e, each investor alters his holdings of bonds by exactly his stockholder's share of the change in debt of each maturity of all firms, and

                                           4                               (5.23)

or equivalently, each investor changes his equity holdings in proportion to the firm's change in total equity capital.  Let us consider the two most natural forms of heterogeneous beliefs.

    Case 1.  For two or more representative individuals i and j, P i(θ(t))  P j(θ(t)).  The two individuals would therefore also disagree on the expected profits to each firm, since these profits are state-contingent.   However, the individuals then disagree as to the returns to firms.  Clearly, Stiglitz's model cannot handle the problems created by this situation, for it implies that the two individuals disagree on the fair price for virtually all, if not all, of the firms in the economy.  If these two individuals represent the beliefs of sizable fractions of the population, then markets will never clear.

    Alternatively, we could say the disagreement over profits to firms across states of the world violates Stiglitz's (1988) assumption of `full and equal access to information on firm earnings.'  Under this interpretation, Stiglitz's model again fails to accommodate the heterogeneous beliefs P i(θ(t))  P j(θ(t)) by construction, rather than by implication.

    Case 2.  Assume the two individuals i and j agree on the probability distribution over states of the world so that P i(θ(t)) = P j(θ(t)) for all .  However, i and j have different priors as to the profits of every firm n for each state of world:  , where   represents the expectation operator for each individual.  Normally the expected value of a variable would be conditioned on each individual's information set.  However, to adhere rigidly to Stiglitz's `full and equal access' requirement, we will assume no one has received any information about earnings.  The individuals are merely endowed with heterogeneous priors as to how profits are distributed across states of the world.  Markets will never clear in this economy, because the individuals cannot agree on fair prices for stocks.  One or more of the individuals will find mispriced stocks and want to buy more claims to those stocks than are available to the market; others may want to sell or supply more shares  at that price than are available.  Thus condition (5.20) will not be met.

    In the Stiglitz (1974) multiperiod MM model, if investors maintain heterogeneous beliefs about the probability distribution over states of the world [P i(θ(t))  P j(θ(t))] or the distribution of profits to firms across states of the world {}, then markets will never clear.  Thus Stiglitz's restated irrelevancy theorem has no consequence even for his own economy.

    Stiglitz also abandoned the MM `risk class' concept in favor of assump­tions that consumers always select the same consumption path and expectations independent of financial policy.  Stiglitz requires these two assumptions to motivate investors to undo the leverage or other financial policy change adopted by firms.  By assuming that individuals believe financial policies have no effect on firm valuation, Stiglitz practically assumes the very object of his proof.

  In contrast, we avoided this unwonted assumption by using the risk class concept.  Section 5.3 shows the MM arbitrage locks in a sure profit even if some `noninfinitesimal group,' or the rest of the market for that matter, believes financial policies matter.  Without the risk class concept, Stiglitz is left with a theorem and a framework that applies only if the economy somehow, magically, reaches equilibrium.  Homogeneous beliefs about each firm's earnings across states of the world clearly define arbitrage opportunities.  Without homogeneous beliefs, individual investors could see arbitrage opportunities directly in conflict with one another. 

    Turning now to the APT, Stambaugh (1983) has argued that the APT applies even when investors have heterogeneous beliefs.  The preceeding arguments concerning heterogeneous beliefs in Stiglitz's reformulation of the MM paradigm apply to Stambaugh's work as well.  In particular, if two or more people disagree over the number of factors, or the returns to firms, or other specifications in the APT, somone may see arbitrage opportunities in prevailing market prices.  In that case, markets will not clear.

    Using a particular factor model (5.16), an individual may decide a given stock is overvalued.  Another individual decides the same stock is undervalued using a different factor model (5.17).  At any given price, one or both of the individuals will continue to show positive or negative excess demand.

    How do we determine who is correct?  Eventually when the state of the world is revealed and actual earnings become common knowledge, we will know which one correctly valued the firm.  Perhaps neither did.  After earnings are announced and their effect on the firm's stock price is revealed, the two would no longer have heterogeneous beliefs over that firm's earnings.  They may continue to employ different factor models and continue to disagree on future earnings.

    Since earnings and the state of nature could prove either of these individuals are correct, each faces some risk - whether he chooses to recognize it - that his own valuation may be wrong.  In the APT with heterogeneous beliefs, everyone can personally believe he sees a riskless arbitrage opportunity, when in reality his investment amounts to risky speculation.  Only an individual who assigns zero probability to his M-factor model being incorrect would be willing to serve as a price dictator and force prices to match his own valuation model. 

    In game theory terminology, the heterogeneous belief investors can each act as Stackelberg leaders.  Without other parties agreeing that their own factor models are inferior and serving as followers, the disparate investors would continually bid against each other.  Prices would continually move up and down with the bids and counter-bids.  The resulting disequilibrium dynamics is known as Stackelberg warfare.

 

 

5.8.  Conclusions and Issues for Future Research

 

This chapter has examined three asset pricing paradigms and found that common knowledge beliefs are not required for the MM model, implicitly assumed in the CAPM, and definitely required for the validity of the APT.  The MM world depicts a stylized view of financial markets with certain simplifying assumptions, for example, no bankruptcy, firm risk classes, and personal borrowing at the same rate as corporate borrowing.  In an effort to eliminate intrinsic uncertainty from their model, MM inserted an additional `imputed rationality' assumption.  As indicated in Section 5.2, the only previous paper to take notice of this missing assumption concluded that the MM results were invalid (unless investors had agreed common knowledge beliefs).  We can relax the `imputed rationality' assumption, which is tantamount to assuming investor beliefs are not only homogeneous but common knowledge, and the key results of the MM model are left intact.  With this analysis, financial economics appears to have taken a step towards relaxing the restrictions on investor beliefs that has plagued the development of most asset pricing theories.

    The absence of common knowledge creates an asymmetric information environment, but the MM arbitrage still holds under this particular dimension of uncertainty.  Any individual can exploit cash flow arbitrage given sufficient resources and a suitably long investment horizon.  Even if some `non-infinitesimal' segment of the market believes debt-equity ratios matter, the MM strategy continues to lock-in a sure profit.  This market segment can be used as a money pump by the rest of the market.

    The CAPM assumes investors know the future returns on assets.  This assumption effectively eliminates capital gains uncertainty and the source of speculation over the unknown beliefs of others.  This strong assumption implies that investor beliefs are common knowledge.  The APT employs homogeneous belief assumptions in an attempt to aggregate individual factor models into a market expression.  However, this attempt falls short due to intrinsic uncertainty inherent in the APT.

    Since the APT uses MM-style arbitrage, why would investor beliefs have to be common knowledge in the APT but not in the MM world itself?  The answer may emerge from the response in Endnote 5 to the disproof the capital structure irrelevancy proposition.  MM arbitrage focuses on identical cash flow streams; the APT emphasizes a murky M-factor model.  Thus the objects of uncertainty are diverse.  It would be like trying to compare the volume of ketchup in two bottles (an objective, measurable fact) with the ingredients that make ketchup taste good (an inherently subjective concept).  Not all arbitrage theories are created equal, even though they employ some variant of MM arbitrage.

    In contrast to Stiglitz (1988), we find that the `risk class' concept is important for MM-style arbitrage, even in Stiglitz's general equilibrium framework.  Without risk classes and homogeneous beliefs, we have no mechanism to eliminate arbitrage opportunities and clear markets.  Without market clearing the applicability of Stiglitz's theorem, on moving from one general equilibrium to another, vanishes.  By reinserting the risk class concept in Sections 5.3 and 5.4, we do not need to restrict individuals to adopt the same consumption path in every equilibrium or to form expectations independent of financial policy.

    Assuming investors have `full and equal access to information on earnings' effectively eradicates, by construction or by implication, the two most natural forms of heterogeneous beliefs:  differing probabilities for states of the world or differing earnings expectations for a firm in a given state of the world.  Thus, while not stated in his theorem, Stiglitz effectively assumes homogeneous investor beliefs like the original MM paradigm.

    At least one issue remains unresolved.  If an individual sees an arbitrage opportunity in either the MM or APT and executes the income arbitrage, what impact does he have on market prices?  Under competitive assumptions, individuals take prices as given and have negligible impact on market prices.  However, various arbitrage pricing models employ the `price dictator' concept, in which any individual can sell an infinite quantity of some asset, if needed, to force the asset's price to adjust and thereby eliminate the arbitrage profit.  If we assume no firm goes bankrupt, should we assume no individual can go bankrupt as well?  If so, then an individual could borrow or sell infinite quantities of assets.

    Intrinsic uncertainty is not merely a technical point but actually an important feature of real world financial markets.  It is all too easy to fall into the trap of labeling certain assets as `undervalued' or `overvalued' or even `a free lunch,' without appreciating the underlying risks involved.  As a case in point, Japanese warrants in 1994 appear to be undervalued.  They are undervalued in comparison to German warrants.  They are undervalued in comparison to shorter term Japanese call options, and they are undervalued in comparison to their historical implied volatilities.

    Nevertheless, only a foolhardy person would rush to buy `undervalued' Japanese warrants based on these facts.  The reasons were outlined in Sections 5.2 and 5.3.  The market contains intrinsic uncertainty, which forces every rational investor to consider the resell potential of his assets based on changes in future market valuations.  The Japanese warrant market could remain in a long-run `undervalued' slump for years.  Any financial institution that tries to execute income arbitrage could have its resources tied up with no return or worse, while it waited for earnings of underlying stocks to grow.  To profit from Japanese warrant trading, arbitrageurs must accurately forecast not only the earnings of the underlying firms, but when these increases in earnings will be reflected in the long-term warrant prices.

    There exists no perfect MM-style arbitrage with Japanese warrants. For example, German warrants are correlated to Japanese warrants, but anyone using German warrants as a hedge is exposed to risk that this correlation will change over time.  Arbitrage desks of investment banks are in the business of managing risks, not simply pursuing `free lunches.'  The risks associated with the absence of common knowledge can be eliminated in the MM world; however, this perfect arbitrage strategy is rarely available in real financial markets.  It is not surprising then that the capital gains motive affects asset prices, which are governed by market sentiment and other intrinsic factors aside from real earnings.

    Having considered the need for common knowledge beliefs assumptions in three asset pricing paradigms, we might wonder how common knowledge assumptions affect the canonical arbitrage pricing model.  The next chapter covers this topic.  We prove a series of `no price exists' propositions and relate the lack of common knowledge to the amount of information about higher-order beliefs revealed by prices.  Chapter 3 emphasized that incomplete markets force everyone to speculate in the sense that optimal consumption bundles cannot be obtained from the available market instruments.  Consequently, everyone plans to retrade.  Chapter 6 shows that speculation based on uncertainty over other traders' (changing) beliefs will tend to be the norm rather than the exception. 


Notes

 

1. I would like to thank Merton Miller, Ronald Shrieves, Robert Jarrow, and Jack Hirshleifer for helpful comments on earlier drafts.  None of the above are responsible for any errors that remain.

 

2. See also Bhattacharya (1979), Myers and Majluf (1984), and Stiglitz (1988).

 

3. Indeed no mechanism in any of the major asset pricing theories transmits this information (about the beliefs of others) to individual investors.

 

4. Grinblatt and Titman (1983) and Stiglitz (1974) claim to have developed equilibrium formulations of the APT and MM paradigms, respectively.  Their models still rely on arbitrage for price adjustments and the absence of arbitrage for market clearing.

 

5. The answer to the ``emperor's clothes disproof'' is as follows.  If an 8 oz. bottle of ketchup sells for $1 and someone offers to buy 16 oz. of ketchup for $3, the market will supply the demander with as much ketchup at that price as he is willing to purchase.  The fact that some `non-infinitesimal' group steps forward to say the volume of ketchup (read earnings of a firm in a given risk class) in two 8 oz. bottles is not equivalent to the volume (read earnings of another firm in that same risk class) in a 16 oz bottle does not preclude the rest of the market from exploiting this arbitrage opportunity.  In fairness, we should note that Burness, Cummings, and Quirk (1980) were aware of similar arguments and found them unpersuasive:  `in effect, this reduces things back to a two-period model, since market values in intervening periods (between now and doomsday) are irrelevant.' (p.62)  Perhaps the matter will remain a philosophical disagreement.

 

6. An investor motivated by capital gains may buy into an `overvalued' stock at present if he believes he can resell it at a profit.  Alternatively, an investor may choose to sell `underval­ued' stock at present with the speculative intent of repurchasing the stock at an even lower price.  From a wealth standpoint, this investment strategy is perfectly rational.

 

 

7. Durand (1989) has noted that pursuing speculative capital gains is more risky than collecting a known dividend.  `But with volatile stock prices, capital losses....are a real possibility.  Dividends represent a bird in the hand; capital gains - representing only one bird in the bush if MM are to be taken literally - may never materialize.'

 

8. See, e.g., the vector analysis in DeMarzo (1988).

 

9. The numerical example also applies to the case of heterogeneous priors.

 

10.    The market's collective judgement about the value of the firm measured as an expected value of future earnings.

 

11.    However, these analyses were complex and their derivations of the APT formula lacked economic intuition, as articulated in the criticism by Shanken (1982).

 

12.    Ross (1976) and Huberman (1982) went to some length to specify the necessary conditions that ensure arbitrage opportunities would apply to any asset deviating from the formula of the APT.  These conditions include von Neumann-Morgenstern utility functions for investors, as well as assumptions on the factor and error distributions.  Yet, as we show in this section, all these restrictive conditions failed to produce true arbitrage opportunities in the absence of common knowledge.

 

13.    Note that we have assumed nothing about investor preferences of the objective function they seek to maximize.

 

14.    Trzcinka (1987) has pointed out that the empirical tests of the APT often find seven or eight significant factors, but one factor predominantly accounts for the variance with the remaining portion split among the other factors tested. 

 

        [I]t is clear from our analysis of the eigenvalues and our chi-squared tests that the question of how many factors (apply to the APT) is far from settled.  Our partial and unsatisfying answer to this question is `at least one.'  In spite of this ambiguity, it is useful to know that the number probably is not zero.  Trzcinka (1987), p.368.

 

        In private correspondence, Richard Roll has disagreed with my characterization of the APT empirical literature as having found that one factor explains most of the return variance.  That conclusion would be expected for empirical models of the return on a large diversified portfolio.  However, for individual stocks, he has found that the first factor generally accounts for 20% of the total variance while the second and higher factors usually account for another 15 to 20 percent.   

 

15.    A similar problem crops up in trying to specify the factors relevant to an individual stock's return from a model applicable to a subset of stocks. 

 

        [T]hese derivations of the APT have been relatively complex and  lacking in economic intuition.  Furthermore, the pricing equation obtained from them does not necessarily hold for any individual asset, even approximately.  This has led some researchers to conclude that the empirical tests of Roll and Ross (1980), Chen ..., Oldfield and Rogalski..., and Brown and Weinstein... are not valid tests of theory....Our model suggests that the existing tests of the APT are appropriate in an economy with non-traded assets.  Grinblatt and Titman (1983), pp.497, 505.

 

        Dhrymes, Friend, and Gultekin (1984) found that standard  tests of the APT require an increasing number of factors as more and more securities are analyzed.  See also Roll and Ross's (1984) reply.

 

16.    Chamberlain and Rothschild (1983) prove that a necessary and sufficient condition for returns to be generated by a K-factor linear model is that K eigenvalues of the covariance matrix of returns grow large as the number of securities increases.

 

17.    Stiglitz's quotation reiterates what we stressed in Section 5.2:  asymmetric information in the MM literature immediately translates into insider (manager or current shareholder) incentives.  In fact, it applies to anyone who is concerned with wealth in addition to income.

 

18.    Smith (1972) and Hellwig (1981) showed how the MM propositions could be extended in an economy that included possible firm bankruptcy.  We omitted a discussion of their models in this chapter, because it entails addition­al specifications for margin contracts.

 


References

 

Bhattacharya, Sudipto, (1979), ``Imperfect Information, Dividend Policy, and `The Bird in the Hand' Fallacy,'' Bell Journal of Economics, Vol. 10:1, pp. 259-270.

 

Breeden, Douglas, (1979), `An Intertemporal Asset Pricing Model with Stochastic Consumption and Investment Opportunities,' Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 7, pp. 265-296.

 

Burness, Stuart, Ronald Cummings, and James Quirk, `Speculative Behavior and the Operation of Competitive Markets Under Uncertain­ty:  A Survey Article,' Staff Paper 80-11, Department of Economics, Montana State University, Bozeman, 1980.

 

Chamberlain, G., and Michael Rothschild, (1983), `Arbitrage, Factor Structure, and Mean-Variance Analysis of Large Asset Markets,' Econometrica, Vol. 51, pp. 1281-1304.

 

DeMarzo, Peter M., (1988), `An Extension of the Modigliani-Miller Theorem to Stochastic Economies with Incomplete Markets and Interdependent Securities,' Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 45, pp. 353-369.

 

Dhrymes, P., I. Friend, and N. Gultekin, (1984), `A Critical Examination of the Empirical Evidence on the Arbitrage Pricing Theory,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 39, pp. 323-347.

 

Durand, David, (1989), `After Thoughts on a Controversy with Modigliani-Miller, Plus New Thoughts on Growth and the Cost of Capital,' Financial Management, Vol. 18:2, pp. 12-18.

 

Dybvig, Philip, (1983), ``An Explicit Bound on Individual Assets' Deviations from APT Pricing in a Finite Economy,' Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 12, pp. 483-496.

 

Grinblatt, Mark, and Sheridan Titman, (1983), `Factor Pricing in a Finite Economy,' Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 12, pp. 497-507.

 

Guth, Michael A. S., and George C. Philippatos, (1987), `A Reexamination of Arbitrage Pricing Theory (APT) under Common Knowledge Beliefs,' Rivista Internazionale di Scienze Economiche e Commerciali, Vol. 36:8, pp. 729-746.

 

Hellwig, Martin F., (1981), `Bankruptcy, Limited Liability, and the Modigl­iani-Miller Theorem,' American Economic Review, Vol. 71, pp. 155-170.

 

Hirshleifer, Jack, (1970), Investment, Interest, and Capital, (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:  Prentice-Hall, Inc.)

 

Huberman, Gur, (1982), `A Simple Approach to Arbitrage Pricing Theory,' Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 28, pp. 183-191.

 

Ingersoll, Jonathan E., (1984), `Some Results in the Theory of Arbitrage Pricing,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 39, pp. 1021-1039.

 

Jarrow, Robert A., (1988), Finance Theory, Englewood Cliffs, N.J., Prentice-Hall, Inc.

 

Keynes, John Maynard, (1936), The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money, (New York:  McGraw Hill).

 

Leland, H. E., and D. H. Pyle, (1977), `Informational Asymmetries, Financial Structure, and Financial Intermediation,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 32, pp. 371-387.

 

Lintner, J., (1969), `The Aggregation of Investors' Diverse Judgments and Preferences in Purely Competitive Security Markets,' Journal of Financial and Quantitative Analysis, Vol. 4, pp. 347-400.

 

Merton, Robert C., (1973), `An Intertemporal Capital Asset Pricing Model,' Econometrica, Vol. 41:5, pp. 867-887.

 

Miller, Merton H., (1988), `The Modigliani-Miller Propositions,' Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 2, pp. 99-120.

 

Modigliani, Franco and Merton H. Miller, (1958), `The Cost of Capital, Corporation Finance, and the Theory of Investment,' American Economic Review, Vol. 48, pp. 261-297.

 

 

 

Modigliani, Franco and Merton H. Miller, (1961), `Dividend Policy, Growth and the Valuation of Shares,' Journal of Business, Vol. 34, pp. 411-433.

 

Mossin, Jan, (1966), `Equilibrium in a Capital Asset Market,' Econometrica, Vol. 32, pp. 768-783.

 

Myers, S. C., and N. S. Majluf, (1984), `Corporate Financing and Investment Decisions When Firms Have Information that Investors Do Not,' Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 11, pp. 187-221.

 

Roll, Richard, and Stephen A. Ross, (1980), `An Empirical Investigation of the Arbitrage Pricing Theory,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 35:5, pp. 1073-1103.

 

Roll, Richard, and Stephen A. Ross, (1984), `A Critical Reexamination of the Empirical Evidence on the Arbitrage Pricing Theory:  A Reply,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 39, pp. 347-350.

 

Ross, Stephen A., (1976), `The Arbitrage Theory of Capital Asset Pricing,' Journal of Economic Theory, Vol. 13, pp. 341-360.

 

    (1977a), `The Determination of Financial Structure:  The Incentive Signalling Approach,' Bell Journal of Economics, Vol. 8:1, pp. 23-40.

 

    (1977b), `Return, Risk, and Arbitrage,' in Risk and Return in Finance, edited by I. Friend and J. Bicksler, (Cambridge, MA:  Ballinger).

 

    (1988), `Comment on the Modigliani-Miller Propositions,' Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 2:4, pp. 127-133.

 

Shanken, Jay, (1982), `The Arbitrage Pricing Theory:  Is It Testable?,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 37, pp. 1129-1140.

 

Sharpe, William F., (1964), `Capital Asset Prices:  A Theory of Market Equilibrium under Conditions of Risk,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 19, pp. 425-442.

 

Smith, Vernon L., (1972), `Default Risk, Scale, and the Homemade Leverage Theorem,' American Economic Review, Vol. 62, pp. 66-76.

 

Stambaugh, Robert, (1983), `Arbitrage Pricing with Information,'         Journal of Financial Economics, Vol. 12, pp. 357-369.

 

Stiglitz, Joseph E., (1969), `A Reexamination of the Modigliani-Miller Theorem,' American Economic Review, Vol. 59, pp. 784-793.

 

    (1974), `On the Irrelevance of Corporate Financial Policy,' American Economics Review, Vol. 64, pp. 851-866.

 

    (1988), `Why Financial Structure Matters,' Journal of Economic Perspectives, Vol. 2, pp. 121-126.

 

Trzcinka, Charles, (1986), `On the Number of Factors in the Arbitrage Pricing Model,' Journal of Finance, Vol. 46:2, pp. 347-368.

 


Comment

 

In reading through (an earlier draft of) the Chapter (5) you gave me, I was reminded of some discussions that Franco Modigliani and I had many years ago on a possible problem with our proof very similar in spirit to the one you point out.  We did not use the term `common knowledge,' of course; that term had not been invented yet.  But we were very definitely aware of the problem.  The missing assumption was noted and introduced not in the 1958 leverage paper, but in the 1961 dividend paper (see p. 427 and especially footnote 24).  The treatment there is admittedly not very rigorous by present day standards.  But at least we sensed an incompleteness that, somewhat to our surprise, no one seems to have followed up prior to your paper.

 

 

Merton H. Miller

Graduate School of Business

University of Chicago

 

 


 

 

 



 

 

    The j th individual's wealth is defined as

                               5                    (5.22)

Combining (5.22) with the accounting identity

                                

6

yields

                          7               (5.23)

 

Finally, the j th individual's consumption in period t is defined as

               

8



[1].

[2]. 

[3].

[4].

[5].

[6].

[7].

[8].

[9].

[10].

[11].

[12].

[13].

[14].

[15].

[16].

[17].

[18].



© Copyright 2007 by Michael A. S. Guth. All Rights Reserved. No portion of this site, including the contents of this web page may be copied, retransmitted, reposted, or duplicated in significant portion without the express written permission of Dr. Michael Guth. Users are always welcome to establish links to this web page or to quote from it freely.